Just Law: A New
Approach to Law and Ethics
*Umer Gilani (2014), submitted to Professor Walsh as Final Paper for Theories of Justice
Table of Contents
INTRODUCTION
In
this essay, I will try to present my own perspective on a simple question which
has occurred to innumerable human beings across the breadth of history: What is
justice? From this question, there flow a couple of others: Must justice always
be “justice according to the law?” Or, can the meaning of justice be discovered
without reference to law? How can we improve our understanding of both law and
justice? This essay is nothing but an attempt to take the reader by one a tour
of the moral universe which I have come to inhabit.
The
exploration begins in Part I at
precisely the point where the whole moral drama of our species begins: the
quest for finding out the meaning of justice in the universe and living their
lives in accordance with a law. I will look at how this quest led first to the
growth of various ethico-legal traditions how, in recent times, it has fostered
schools of Enlightenment philosophy which seek to uncover the meaning of
justice in isolation from the historically accumulated systems of law. In Part II, I show how the Enlightenment
projects which ascribe no independent ethical value to the law, and seek to
conceive the meaning of justice purely through ethical theory, have failed and
led us into an impasse. In Part III,
I review the experience of two key counter-revolutions sparked by the
Enlightenment: fundamentalism and spiritualism. Scriptural fundamentalists have
tried to understand the law through formalist readings of scripture and without
engaging in any theory of justice. They too have failed. I argue that their
failure proves that that while justice must always be justice according to the
law, we cannot properly understand the meaning of law with developing a theory
of justice. Spiritualists, contend that while the meaning of justice can be
understood by individuals, it is an incommunicable truth knowable only by the
heart. Spiritualism offers no possibility of ever having a socially-shared
sense of justice. Where philosophers and fundamentalists have failed,
spiritualists refuse even to try.
Together,
Parts I, II and III lead us to the conclusion that projects of trying to find
law and justice in isolation from each other have failed; those of us engaged
in the ethico-legal quest need to focus our efforts on understanding law and
justice through their relationship with each other, rather than in isolation
from eachother. What humanity needs today is neither pure Justice, nor pure Law,
but what I have termed “Just Law”.
In
Part IV, I argue that a search for
Just Law inevitably leads us into the realm of various ethico-legal traditions
which grew out of the scriptures over the course of human history. The very
idea of scriptural law is that the Law (Law in a higher sense) enjoys normativity
independent of ethics. By affirming the independent normativity of the Law,
these traditions allow law and ethics to engage constructively, without either
obliterating the other. That said, scriptural traditions offer the possibility
of delivering Just Law for our times, only when interpreted through a
particular interpretative approach. In Part
V, I propose the contours of one such approach to interpreting scriptures in
the briefest outlines. I suggest that in order to be revived, scriptural
ethico-legal interpretation must incorporate the ever-greater insights being offered
by the sciences of Nature, History and Society. In this part, I also offer a
few practical examples of problems where Just Law offers better solution than
either Enlightenment ethical philosophy or scriptural fundamentalism. In Part
VI, I argue that Just Law promises to practitioners and professors of law
something they stand in need of: a renewed meaning for the legal calling and
restoring legal education to the centrality that it once enjoyed amongst the
human sciences. The concluding Part VII touches
upon the philosophical methodology of this essay.
PART I
The Dawn
of the Human Ethico-Legal Quest: From Tradition to the Enlightenment
1.
A Question That Must Be Answered
The
words “law” and “justice” may be particular to one language; but they point out
to a concept which is found in so many different societies that we can conclude
that these are indeed “universal” questions. It is fair, then, to begin this
discourse by thinking about why it is that you and I may need to bother about
law and justice and why it is that so many human beings before have actually bothered
about law and justice.
The
biological make-up of the homo sapiens bears
a striking resemblance to other animals in the mammalian family, and
particularly the primates amongst them. Yet, our species differs from all the others
in a number of very significant ways. The most widely recognized amongst our
distinctly human traits is our ethico-legal quest. At some point or another in
our lives, most of us begin to feel an inner urge to find out the answer to the
question “What shall I do? How shall I live?” Up until this point, which we may
call the moment of ethico-legal awakening, the human being lives its life with
the same resources that all animal use: the habits of the body (“instinct”) and
the habits of mind (“custom”). For the awakened human being however, these sure
guides are no longer sufficient; what the awakened human being now looks for is
a knowledge of what is right and just. In these fateful moments of ethical
awakening, the human gaze turns from the tricks of daily survival to the wonders
of the starry heavens above us and the moral law within us. The human develops
what I shall, in the rest of this essay, the ethico-legal quest.
Why
do we develop this urge to find out what is good and just?
May
be it is because we cannot bear the thought that the fate that we see befalling
all other animals – death and decay – is going to be ours too. Animals have
been able to confronts death with serenity because they have never had to think
about what comes later. But humans have a consciousness of their being alive which
is far too acute to allow them to live in this state of blissful ignorance. The
human beings’s acute consciousness of life compels him to think about the
after-life. Those who begin to think of the after-life are generally unable to
suffer the conclusion that death and decay is our ultimate end. Once we humans conclude
that our fate after death is different from other animals, it only follows that
our life here on earth too much be lived in accord with a different code; while
instinct and custom suffice for animals, the human needs more. By his nature,
the human years, perhaps, for knowledge of the starry heavens that sees above
him and the moral law which he finds residing within him.
Or
may be we embark upon the ethico-legal quest, taking a cue held out to us by
nature (or whoever we perceive as the Creator). That cue lies in language. The
fact that we can speak to each other about law and justice unlike animals who
can only make sounds expressing pain and pleasure, suggests that we should
indeed speak about law and justice, not just pain and pleasure. Aristotle notes
this in a beautiful passage in his Politics:
Nature, according to our theory,
makes nothing in vain; and man alone of the animals is furnished with the
faculty of language. The mere making of
sounds serves to indicate pleasure and pain, and is thus a faculty that
belongs to animals in general; their nature enables them to attain the point at
which they have perceptions of pleasure and pain, and can signify those
perceptions to one another. But language
serves to declare what is advantageous and what is the reverse, and it is the peculiarity
of man, in comparison with other animals, that he alone possesses a perception
of good and evil, of the just and the unjust, and other similar qualities.[1]
2.
The Traditional Response: The Emergence of Ethico-legal traditions
Our
quest for the moral law has, over the course of thousands of years of recorded human
history, given birth to innumerable ethico-legal traditions. Awakened human have
stumble upon answers to their question in various ways. Firstly, there are
those who find the answers in mystical
experience, which answers the profoundest questions of life but the results are
of an essentially incommunicable nature and remain unknown to all but the
recepient. Secondly, there are those amongst the possessors of mystical
experience who are able to articulate their results in the highly ambiguous and
generalized medium of poetry.
Thirdly, there are those who are able to venture sophisticated conjectures
using the intellect; but the answers
of the intellect to the deepest human questions have, as we shall explore later
in this essay, always been essentially indeterminate; it is as though the
intellect has, on its own, never able to pierce the veil of multiplicity of
phenomena and reach the unitary reality which lies behind it. Finally, there
are those who receive answers to the ethico-legal questions through prophetic experience, i.e some prophet’s
direct encounter (or professed encounter) with the law of God or nomos. the results of which are composed
in the form of scriptures.
One
of the most remarkable facts of the human history is that the answers to the
ethico-legal question that have proved the most durable and widely accepted in society
are the ones that the flowed out of some prophetic experience. Another
interesting fact about the ethico-legal traditions that have survived the test
of time, and particularly the Jewish, Islamic, Hindu, Catholic and Daoist traditions,
is that in these traditions, one’s understanding of justice is never completely
detached from one’s understanding of the law. Law and justice are viewed as
inextricably related rather than isolated. Unlike our mainstream contemporary
understanding of law, the primary concern of these ethico-legal traditions has
not the rules that govern adjudication by a state of rights claims between persons.
The primary concern of the ethico-legal traditions has been to answer the basic
human question of “how ought I to live? what shall I do?” However, through
prescribing the rules for living a good life, these traditional also lay down
the basis for another subset: rules for adjudication of rights between persons.
Since their concern is ethical as well as legal, in these traditions, a
detailed study of the contours of the law is deemed indispensible for
developing a proper sense of justice; conversely, having a deep concern for
justice is deemed indispensible for understanding the contours of the law
properly.
The
Christian tradition began with undermining the centrality that the Jewish
ethico-legal tradition had accorded to the Law. In his second letter to the
Corinthians, the Apostle Paul proclaims that “[God] has made us able ministers
of the new testament — not of the letter, but of the Spirit; for the letter
killeth, but the Spirit giveth life.”[2] This
was bold assault on the ethic value of the law. Yet, the truth is that over the
course of most of its history, Christians did not abolish the ethical value of
their law, the law of the Jewish people; they sought only to shift the balance
between the Spirit and the Law toward the former.
I
do not intend to suggest that all ancient ethico-legal tradition offered a unanimous
view of the relationship between law and ethics; they did not. But I do
consider worth pointing out what all the ancients seemed to agree upon: the
relationship between law and justice is not a simple binary, a one-way train,
with ethic being determined first, and the law only following. It is understood
that just as law and ethics cannot have a one-on-one overlap, so too there
cannot be an absolute divorce between them; they over-lap and inter-relate in
complex ways. In The Queen v. Dudley and
Stephens, confronted with a particularly tricky case of high-seas
cannibalism, Lord Coleridge, C.J. of the British Court of Appeals, states the
ancient understanding in the following words:
Though law and morality are not the
same, and many things may be immoral which are not necessarily illegal, yet the
absolute divorce of law from morality would be of fatal consequence…[3]
3.
Enlightenment’s Challenge to the Ethico-Legal Tradtions: the Isolation of Ethics from Law
In
the post-Christian Enlightenment period, however, this sophisticated and
nuanced understanding of the problem begins to disappear. We find amongst
ethical philosophers a total neglect for this subtle inter-relatedness of law
and ethics. Ethical philosophers of this period seem to be taking Apostle Paul
on his word, by attempting to find the meaning of justice without any reference
to prior legal tradition. What they seem to have ignored is the subtext of
Paul’s statement: the Law that killeth, and the Spirit that saveth, depend on
each other for their very existance: the savior exists, because the killer does
too. The one can never be understood without reference to the other; indeed, it
could not even exist without the other.
The
leading exponents of the post-Christian Enlightenment period, however, do not
seem have a fair appreciation of this subtle, complicated and seemingly
contradictory relationship between law and morality. They complain about how
“the rarest of all human qualities is consistency”[4]
and how “morality itself remains subjected to all sorts of corruption as long
as [a] guiding thread, [an] ultimate norm
of correct moral judgment, is lacking.[5]
Discontent with the lack of absolute deductive consistency, and a deep yearning
for one “ultimate norm” characterizes Enlightenment philosophers’ forays into
law and ethics. What they are hoping is to discover the one ethical truth from
which all other truths can then be deductively,
unthinkingly and definitively derived; it is in the field of law and ethics the
necessary outgrowth of the foundationalist project. The quest is definitely: it
promises the certainty of deduction, whereas the law has always had to contend
with the indeterminacy of induction; and it offers moral confidence where morality
has generally had to contend with continuing doubt. But the question is: can
such ethical truth ever be found?
The
two most significant such projects in the field of law have been those of the
Benthamites and Kantians, which we examine here briefly.
Following
in the footsteps of Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill complains that “the
nonexistence of an acknowledged first principle has made ethics not so much a
guide as a consecration of men’s actual sentiments…”. To provide a surer
knowledge of right and wrong, he demands:
[T]here ought to be some one
fundamental principle or law, at the root of all morality, or if there be
several, there should be a determinate order of precedence among them; and the
one principle, or the rule for deciding between the various principles when
they conflict, ought to be self-evident.” [6]
For
the Utilitarians, this one principle or law at the root of all genuine morality
is the principle of Utility. Mill states the creed of utilitarianism in the
following words:
[A]ctions are right in proportion
as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of
happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by
unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure.[7]
For
all his differences, Kant shares with the Utilitarians this urge for a single
moral truth from which all others can be deductively, unthinkingly and
definitively defined. He stresses “the utmost importance [of] forg[ing] for
once a pure moral philosophy, completely cleansed of everything that may be
only empirical and that really belongs to anthropology” After a detailed
inquiry, Kant is able to discover a “pure” conception of law and ethics which
he states thus: “Act as though the maxim of your action were to become by your
will a universal law of nature.”[8]
For Kant, once this one ethical principle has been discovered, all law can be
deductively, unthinkingly and definitively derived from it.
While
the academic debate between these two schools of ethics continues, it is
important is to look at the fate of the political and juristic projects which
Enlightenment thought fostered. Both Utilitarians and Kantians have fostered a
series of approaches to the law to which we now turn. I mention, albeit
briefly, the following Enlightenment projects which attempted to reconstruct
the law in accord with pre-determined foundational notions of justice: the Communist assault on the
traditional notions of property law and distributive justice; the Feminist
assault on traditional notions of family law; and Hedonism’s assault on traditional notions of prohibited
spleasures.
All
of these Enlightenment projects of law reform emanated from well-meaning
efforts by ethical philosophers who were deeply perturbed by injustices
perpetrated and justified in the name of the legal tradition. They responded by
denying any intrinsic value to the existing laws, and by trying to determine
the meaning of justice in isolation from them. The hope was that sure
principles of justice are determined, legal rulings could then be deduced
axiomatically from them, leading to perfectly just outcomes. At first, these
essentially Cartesian projects looked certainly tempting. They promised to
resolve all moral problems with clarity and certainty without requiring any
much intellectual or ethical effort from lawyers or citizens (save the
philosopher who discovers the first principles.
But the promise remains unfulfilled.
Perhaps
it is time to concede that a unidirectional, binary conception of law and
ethics has not succeeded in providing us any moral compass with which to our
personal and collective lives. Instead, it has led, in many cases, to
unparalleled disasters which should make any careful observer highly cautious
about the whole project. This search represents in the field of law and ethics
the equivalent of the medieval alchemists’ search for the Sorcerer’s stone in
the field of Chemistry.
PART
II
The Dreams
That Turned Sour: Failures of doing Ethics without Law
1.
Egalitarianism and the Road to Totalitarinism
One
of the most evident problems that the human condition confronts us with is the
problem of distribution. (Almost) everyone desires the good things of the
world. Yet, most of us cannot have everything we want, because others must have
something too. The question that the morally awakened human being begins to ask
himself is: What portion for each would
be a just portion? When he looks around himself in the world with this question
in mind, he confronts a world marked by a staggering distributive. A few have a
lot (guaranteed to them by the law) and most have very little. This disturbs
the conscience and creates serious doubts in the mind of the morally awakened
human being. He asks: How can a law which gives so much to some and so little
to others, be just and good? Far more than the envy which Oliver Wendell Holmes
and Hayek complain of, it is this instinctively human curiosity about the normative
basis of distributive inequality which motivates those who blow the trumpet of social
justice.
At
this point in his intellectual quest, one solution that occurs to the morally
awakened mind is based on the idea of Equality and merit. This solution seems
simple: like things must be treated alike; insofar as human beings are alike,
they are entitled to the good things of the world equally; it is only where one
person possesses a special “merit” that he can be entitled to something extra. Any
legal entitlement that cannot be traced back to principles of Equality (and
merit) is an unjust, unmerited
entitlement; it must be abolished. Any law which supports such unjust
entitlements must also be abolished - or so the morally awakened human at this
juncture thinks.
But
when the morally awakened mind begins to use this concept for deriving legal
outcomes in actual matters concerning the rights of human beings, a practical
difficulty arises: how do we determine the “merit” of a human being? Does this
not require from society passing a definitive judgment about the “worth” of
defenseless individual human being? In other words, the egalitarian conception
of distributive justice necessarily requires some external person or community
to pass a judgment upon the “worth” of individual human beings. This can be far
more degrading to people than treating them unequally.
That
the ethical principle of Equality leads us into certain insoluble philosophical
quandaries is not a twentieth century discovery. Even as far back as Aristotle,
philosophers could envisage it clearly. Here is what Aristotle says in his
Politics:
Justice is
considered to mean equality. It does mean equality – but equality for those who
are equal, and not for all. Again, inequality is considered to be just; and
indeed it is – but only for those who are unequal, and not for all. … There is
general agreement about what constitutes equality in the thing, but disagreement about what constitutes it in
the people.”[9]
The
worth of the human being, this most mysterious of all the universe’s wonders, has
defied all efforts at objective measurement. If we cannot measure the merit of
a human being, then how can be declare him as equal or unequal to another human
being?
Aristotle’s
proposed solution to this seemingly intractable philosophical quandary – the
indeterminacy of the merit of a human being vis-à-vis other human beings – is
to look at a human being’s contribution for the “polis” or the political community. He says:
Those who contribute most to the polis have a greater share in the city
than who are equal to them (or even greater) in free birth and descent. [10]
A
perceptive reader should be able to see the danger that lurks in the practical
enforcement of this well-intentioned prescription: when one’s share of the good
things of the world is determined entirely in accordance with the categorical
imperative of “Equality”, then the political community must become the ultimate
arbiter of one’s merit as well as livelihood. Making the political community the
arbiter of the individual’s livelihood compromises his political freedoms; and
making the individual’s worth socially measurable robs him of his inner dignity
and pride.
The
swiftness with which both Communist and National Socialist regimes in pre-WWII
Europe and post-WWII former colonies morphed into totalitarian governments had
much to do with this theoretical problem inherent in the ethical principle of
Equality. While communist legality and National Socialist legality were meant,
from the beginning to be different from the then-existing conception of rule of
law, totally arbitrariness was certainly not on the agenda. Yet, once the
legitimacy of the (bourgeiosie’s) historically accumulated legal traditions had
been demolished, the people soon found out that they had little left to protect
themselves with from oppression. Everywhere, the opporession started with
property-less majorities tyrannizing propertied minorities in communist states
and ethnic/religious majorities tyrannizing minorities in fascist states; but
it did not stop there. Soon all power ended up in the hands of small governing
cliques and the majorities too had to suffer.
What
this experience showed is that a society in which the ideal of Equality is
taken to its logical extreme is a society where the distribution of goods takes
place through the central planning, in the hope that each will get precisely
what he “deserves”. Friedrich Hayek acutely perceived the dangers that the
principle of Equality poses to historically accumulated rule of law and, in
turn, to human dignity. In the Constitution of Liberty he stated:
[T]he mark of a free man is to be
dependent for his livelihood not on other people’s views of his merit but
solely upon on what he has to offer them.… A society in which it was generally
presumed that a high income was proof of merit and a low income of the lack of
it, in which it was universally believed that position and remuneration
correspond to merit, in which there was no other road to success than the
approval of one’s conduct by the majority of one’s fellows, would probably by
much more unbearable to the unsuccessful ones than one in which it was frankly
recognized that was no necessary connection between merit and success. [11]
Most
historically accumulated legal systems lay down a complex regime of rules for
determining existing property rights, as well as rules for further accumulation
of property. By and large, they leave the distribution of goods to the forces
that prevail in the market. These legal rules do not deductively flow either
from the principle of Equality or the principle of Liberty; instead, they
strikes rough but nuanced balance between the two; it is these balances which
make the legal field such labyrinth. Egalitarian ethical philosophy’s solution
to the problem of distribution - central planning – is far more neat. Initially,
it tramples the old rules in name of furthering Equality. But eventually it
ends up compromising both Equality and Liberty, making things far worse than
before. It is only when the imperfect but useful historically evolved rule of
law is gone that its value is true felt and its subtleties appreciated.
2.
Utilitarianism and the Road to Communism: The Abolition of Property Law for the
General Good
Utilitarians
may not own up to it, but the most daring assault on the major legal traditions
of the world over the last century – the communist abolition of private
property – stemmed directly from the philosophical foundations which they had
furnished. The idea of private property enjoys a respectable a lineage in
almost all the great legal traditions of the world. The ius civile of the Romans, the Talmud
of the Jews, the Shariah of
Muslims, the Dharmashastras of the
Hindus, Canon law and natural law of the Catholics, English common law, and the
Chinese Dao fully recognized that at
least some parts of the world’s resource can be legitimately owned by
individuals. Before utilitarians eroded the legitimacy of the law as a moral
guide, to jurists steeped in these ethico-legal traditions, the very idea of
abolishing private property altogether would have seemed unthinkable. Plato could
certainly toy with a proposal for a certain kind of communism in his Republic, and Aristotle could counter those
arguments in Politics; but in actual
practice it was the worldly wisdom of lawyers that was supposed to prevail, of
course. That is what changed with the Enlightenment.
When
philosophers refused to give the law any independent normativity, the grounds
were laid for something radical. When the utilitarians claimed that any law
which did not conduce to their one-line ethical creed - the avoidance of pain
and the promotion of happiness - could be dispensed with, they meant “any” law.
Even as fundamental a legal notion as private property became fair game for
reform on ethical grounds.
Almost
a century after the Bolshevik Revolution in Russia, and a half century after
the Cultural Revolution in China, the economic consensus seems to be clear. The
abolition of private property has been found by experience to be devastating
for general economic welfare: it did not promote happiness or avoid pain. The
traditional legal concept of private property has stood its ground. But this
vindication of an ancient legal proposition has not come cheap. When left at the
mercy of ethical philosophy, we have managed to verify one legal proposition
only at the loss of the lives and livelihoods of millions of innocent human
beings.
At
this juncture in history, honest lawyer and philosopher cannot help but have
serious doubts about the bold enterprise of reinventing the law in the light of
rather fickle and oft-shifting rational understandings of what conduces to
Utility and what does not. At the theoretical level, if there is anything that
the Communist tinkering with fundamental legal notions should have taught us,
it is this: ethical philosophy is good fun, but the wisdom of the law as it has
historically evolved, and as it presently exists, must never again be taken
lightly
The
assault on traditional notions of property law has not just come from the
various cults of Utilitarians. Kantians believe that all law rules must be
based upon the categorical imperative of “do unto others as you shall have do
unto yourself” Because no one who treats another unequally would suffer himself
to be treated unequally, every rule in the rule book that does not fit the
principle of Equality is to be scrapped. Kantian too have also found themselves
at odds with various branches of historically evolved law, especially family
law.
3.
Egalitarianism, Feminist Family Law and the Breakdown of the Human Family
Feminism
is presently doing to our regimes of family law what communism did to our
private law in the last century: reinventing the entire set of the rules of the
game in line with a single ethical principle.
This
involves reconceiving all the male-female ethico-legal relationships, including
the mother-son, father-daughter, brother-sister relationship, which lie at the
heart of family law. But much more than these biological relationships, feminism’s
focus is on that one family relationship where, arguable, it is the law and not
biology which plays a primary role: the marital relationship. An interesting fact
about traditional legal rulings on the marital relationship is that almost nowhere
in the pre-modern world was it conceived of as a relationship between absolute equals.
The rights of both spouses have everywhere been substantial and defined in law,
but they have never before been precisely equal. The idea that marriage is a
contract between absolute equals
would have been inconceivable to jurists trained in anything from the ius civile to the Shariah, halakha, dharma, canon law and English common law. The
scriptures of the Judeo-Christian and Islamic tradition do talk about the male
and the female having been created from a “single soul”, thus hinting at significant equality between the two;
but any honest interpreter has to concede that there is no mention of absoluted legal equality of husbands and
wives in the scriptures, while indications to contrary abound. Such
interpretations have been put upon the scriptures in the twentieth century, but
the historical norm has clearly been different.
The
egalitarian conception of family law became possible only when the inner
morality of the legal tradition got totally displaced by ethical philosophy,
particularly in the Kantian tradition. What has resulted from this is the
feminist jurisprudence of the late twentieth century. Using the a priori principle of equality, the
whole legal corpus dealing with the marital relationships has been reinvented.
The requirements regarding entry into marriage (capacity, consent, dower etc.),
rights during it (conjugal rights, right to maintenance, right to earn
property, reasonable chastisement) and exit from it (grounds for divorce,
children’s custody, alimony) have been radically altered. Whereas previously
each spouse enjoyed advantages over the other in some matters and disadvantages
in other matter, the new jurisprudence seeks to equalize them in all matters. The
historically accrued rules of family law reflect compromise between principles
of Equality and Inter-dependence, often inspired by scriptures, but effectively
worked out by the law over centuries of interpretation, are no longer accorded any independent normative
values; the only thing sacred is the principle of equality and all that impedes
its path must give way.
Whatever
the merits of this arrangement may be, empirical evidence suggests that the new
family law is failing badly. Historically accumulated legal traditions may have
defied the logic of equality in various cases; but at least they succeeded in
keeping the institution of family alive and growing. Regardless of one’s
normative assessment of the present situation, wherever in the word the new
rationalist family law has been established, we see the human family as an
institution in decline. People are marrying later in life than ever before; and
many are not marring at all, resorting to less permanent forms of cohabitation.
The few who marry are unable to stay married for long. Children being born
under wedlock are on the point becoming a minority; even those who are born
under wedlock are unable to enjoy the secure childhood that the multiple-parent
family once ensured to most of the young of our species. While human beings used
to live their adult lives with spouses, families and kin groups during much of
our history, increasingly, they find themselves living in single-person
households.
The evidence establishing a correlation
between the two phenomena - the Enlightenment’s reconception of family law and
the decline of the family - is so overwhelming that only a most bigoted
observer can fail to notice it. Correlation is not causation, but the odds are
high thatt there is at least something the former has contributed to the
latter. If this is so, then for many of us, it is no longer possible to view
the ethico-legal principle of human Equality with the same enthusiasm once had
for it. May be, this Philosophers’ Stone is simply incapable of providing the legal
foundations for stable and fulfilling marital relationships and we have no
choice but to return to the historically accumulated rules of family law.
4.
Libertarian Inroads into the world of prohibited pleasures: The hedonist spiral
Almost
all the great traditional ethico-legal systems of the world comprehensively regulated
the human being’s enjoyment of primal pleasures of life: food, drink, sex and
stupor. The Islamic Shariah, the Jewish
halakha, the Brahmancial dharma, Catholic natural law, the
Chinese Dao and African tribal laws
all provide an elaborate list of prohibitions on what a person subject to the law
can (at least publically) consume and what forms of sexual relations he is
entitled to engage in. In recent years, we have experienced an intensified
assault on the few amongst these legal rules that have remained enforceable. This
conflict is hardly surprising. None of the old systems of rules fits neatly with
the stringent tests of utilitarianism and libertarianism. So, for instance,
almost all of these ethico-legal traditions prohibit or greatly restrict the
enjoyment of mind-altering drugs, ranging from alcohol to cannabis and marijuana.
Most traditions also place restrictions
on various forms of sexual conduct, including the conduct of fully-informed and
freely consenting persons: fornication, adultery, incest, homosexuality,
sado-masochism and anal intercourse (even with a spouse) etc. These ethico-legal
traditions have gone so far as to proscribe sexual conduct which involves only
one person – such as viewing pornography or engaging in masturbation.
These
prohibitions are rooted in a complex set of reasons which new natural lawyers
such as John Finnis[12] and
Germain Grisez[13]
have recently made a commendable attempt to articulate, especially from a
Catholic natural law perspective. For the present we are not concerned with
establishing the reason behind these legal rules. What we do need to understand
is that it is only understandable if there rules run afoul with simple logics
of Utilitarianism and Libertarianism because they emerged from a totally
difference view about the relationship between law and morality.
Kant restricted the role of the rule’s enforcement
of law. For him, the ruler has no business assisting a community in their ethico-legal
quest; his business is only to keep peace between them. Advising the ruler, at
a time when the ruler’s word was the law, he says:
Salvation is none of [the ruler’s]
business; it is his business to prevent one man from forcibly keeping another
from determining and promoting his salvation to the best of his ability. [14]
Half a century later, by John Stuart Mill’s time, not
only the ruler who enforces the law, but the law itself, supposed to stay clear
of any notion of ethics. Mill famously summarized the Libertarian position in
the following words:
The only purpose for which power
can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against
his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral,
is not sufficient warrant. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do or forbear
because it will be better for him to do so, because it will make him happier,
because, in the opinion of others, to do so would be wise, or even right...”[15]
Once a curtain is drawn between the law’s value as a
protector of individual’s liberty, and its value as the guide to the ethical
good, it is only natural that the older laws can no longer stand. Adults
engaging in consensual anal sex, extra-marital sex, homosexual and incestuous conduct,
watching pornography and smoking and injecting mind-altering drugs do not cause
“harm” to others in the ordinary sense of the word. They do, arguably, harm
themselves by deviating from the model of life which our ethico-legal systems
went lengths to elucidate. Trying to defend these prohibitions within the
parameters of Utilitarian or Libertarian reasoning in not only dishonest but
impossible. The ethico-legal systems which gave birth to these rules never confined
their objectives to protecting our Liberty, ensuring our Equality or enhancing
our Utility. In those systems, the Law was concerned quite unabashedly with elaborating
the meaning of a truly ethical life for the community; the functional and
ethical elements of the Law were not seen in binary terms.
Take,
for instance, the case of the definition of marriage in English common law,
which is subject of such a charged debate, in the wake of the popularity of
homosexual lifestyle in the United States. Classical jurists of the common law
tradition always viewed marriage as “the union between man and one woman”; the
argument that marriage could be redefined as a union between any kind and
number of consenting adults would have flown over their head. This is so
because even common law jurists, perhaps the most secularized of all ancient
jurists, were still concerned, fundamentally, with propagating through the law an
ethical vision of dealing with sexual urge. In their writings, jurists of the
common law sought to distance themselves from the ethical content of the law they
were expounding, leaving these matter for the ecclesiastical authorities. So Blackstone
tries to separate law and ethics by claiming that the common law “considers
marriage in no other light than as a civil contract. The Holiness of the
matrimonial state is left entirely to our ecclesiastical law…” Yet, even he is
forced to acknowledge that “common lawyers … indeed have borrowed (especially
in ancient times) almost all of their notions of the legitimacy of marriage
from the canon and civil law.”[16] These
foundations of the English law of marriage – Roman ius civile and Catholic canon law - were by no means concerned just
with a fair distribution of rights between spouses; they were concerned with
promoting a certain conception of the good sexual life, and discouraging other
approaches to sexuality.
The
roots of our present marriage-related legal dilemmas go back to the time when
the ethical conception of marriage law got displaced by a libertarian
conception. This culminated first in the legalization of adultery, fornication
and homosexuality in the 1960s and 1970s. Once the law no longer claimed to be
promoting a certain ethical view about proper human sexuality, it was only
inevitable that the very definition of marriage too would come under attack.
If, under the new libertarian creed, marriage law can no longer serve the
function of propagating a society’s vision of good sexuality, then on what grounds
can society deny homosexuals an entry into the institution of marriage. In
other words, the passage from decriminalization of “deviant” sexuality on
libertarian ground to the inclusion of sexual “deviants” into the fold of
marriage is a logically necessary move; that societies are now heading in this
direction should surprise no one.
The
erosion of these rules on prohibited pleasures which we are seeing since the
1960’s in various parts of the world, especially the post-Enlightenment
Christian West, is precisely what is to be expected once a society buys into
Mill’s notion that the law has no business guiding us about the ethical life. America’s
most brilliant conservative jurist, Justice Antonin Scalia, confronted this
issue head on in Barnes v. Glen Theatre,
Inc.[17],
while defending the constitutionality of a ban on fully nude female dancing in the
state of Indiana. In his concurrence, he clarified that the legal ban in
question did not exist merely to prevent “harm”; it existed in order to project
American society’s vision of what a moral sexual life is. He stated:
Our society prohibits, and all
human societies have prohibited, certain activities not because they harm
others but because they are considered, in the traditional phrase, "contra bonos mores," i. e.,
immoral. In American society, such prohibitions have included, for example,
sadomasochism, cockfighting, bestiality, suicide, drug use, prostitution, and
sodomy.
In American society at large, growing skepticism
about the ethical basis of the legal rulings on prohibited pleasures has been
growing since the failure of the ill-fated prohibition project in the early
part of the century. In Lawrence v.
Texas,[18]
despite Scalia’s eloquent dissent, the
Supreme Court’s majority finally over-ruled Barnes
v. Glen, thus eroding the constitutional basis of all “morals legislation”.
If the logic of Lawrence is followed
to its conclusion, the whole gamut of American laws dealing with prohibited
pleasures might soon have to be abolished. Scalia’s harm-less “evils” -
sadomasochism, cockfighting, bestiality, suicide, drug use, prostitution, and
sodomy, and other acts which he did not name - would have be legalized. Actually,
many of these are already legal.
What the new trend seems to ignore is an insight
offered by most of the world’s ethico-legal systems: the law is by its very
nature a vehicle for ethics. The only question that a society must pose itself
is: whose ethics shall our law propagate? Libertarianism’s inroads in the legal
regulation of prohibited pleasures claim to be ethically neutral; but the reality
is that it too is promoting a certain view of the good life at the cost of
other views, just as the old laws used to. The only difference is that this
time the vision of good life being propagated by the law is not the Biblical
morality espoused by America’s silent majority, but the hedonist morality of a
privileged minority.
5.
Capitalism and the Decriminalization of Wealth Addiction.
Imbalanced
approaches to sexuality and mind-altering drugs are, of course, far from the
greatest danger to human welfare on earth. Historically, the greatest danger to
human welfare has been posed by an imbalanced approach to wealth. And one of
the Enlightenment’s greatest ethico-legal failures lies is its inability to restrain
this imbalance. The problem is of ancient origins. Every ethico-legal system of
the world has had to confront it.
The
primary question to be asked is not the legal question on the limits of
permissible wealth. The primary question is a psychological question: why are
human beings unable to control their drive for wealth in order to allow others
in the world, and indeed themselves, a better life? Up to a certain amount, the
acquisition of wealth contributes positively to human being’s happiness and
that of others too. But once they learn the art of acquiring wealth, human
beings have a tendency of get addicted to it. The wealth addict finds himself
unable to stop accumulating more and more wealth. The wealth addict is no
longer able to enjoy the benefits of what he has, and he also deprives others
of what they could have had, creating great misery in the world. Wealth
addiction became a problem especially so in the era that dawned after the rise
of currency.
Before
the invention of money and the rise of trade, this was not such an acute problem,
as noted by John Lock (Justice: A Reader, pp. 93 – 95)The wealth of people who
made their living by hunting, gathering,
grazing and growing consisted mostly of edibles
that were non-durable and could not be endless possessed. Furthermore,
the safety valves against addiction to food and drink are in-built features of
the human body. Our appetite for food and drink (except mind-altering drugs) is
quite limited; we can commit a few excess but soon enough, the body’s defenses
kick in and we feel sate. The problem is more acute in the case of sexuality,
especially male sexuality, where the bodily restraints on excess are less
strong. But in the case of currency, the defenses are simply not there. So, for
as long as we lived on subsistence and edibles were the sum total of the wealth
we would acquire, the chances of getting addicted to the acquisition of wealth
were minimal. But when, due to the rise of trade, currency (gold, silver etc.) entered
the scene around three to four millennia ago, the game changed.
Currency
allowed for a concentration of wealth that was previously not technically
possible. The problem with currency is
that it is a form of wealth that exists purely in the mind. It does not rot and
it does make its bearer sate. In simple words, while one man could never have eaten
or drank all the edibles in the world earlier, leaving all others hungry now he
could, at least theoretically, own all the trade-able wealth in the world, by
monopolizing all currency, leaving others penniless. Soon after the emergence
of money, something like this might have actually happened. The era after the
emergence of currency is marked by the rise massively wealthy individuals,
often kings, like Abraham’s nemesis, the
Babylonian Nimrod and Moses’ nemesis, the Egyptian Pharoah. Even today, things are not all that different; the 85
richest people own a larger share of the world’s wealth than half of all the
world’s population, ie. 3.5 billion people. And if the total wealth of the
world were divide into two halves, one half would be owned by the richest 1%;
the other 99% would have to share the other half amongst themselves.[19] Long
after the ear of the Pharoahs, we are still struggling to tame the problem of
distributive inequality.
A recent op-ed by Sam Polkjan a former wealth
addict from the Wall Street capture these problems beautifully. It may be
quoted here brielfly:
Like
alcoholics driving drunk, wealth addiction imperils everyone. Wealth addicts
are, more than anybody, specifically responsible for the ever widening …vast
and toxic disparity between the rich and the poor…” The problem he notes is
that “[o]ur culture supports and even lauds the addiction. Look at the magazine
covers in any newsstand, plastered with the faces of celebrities and C.E.O.'s;
the superrich are our cultural gods.” The most decisive change that the
Enlightenment made is not in allowing liberal economic laws; the liberal
economic law of the Enlightenment have robbed the law of its ethical message
which used to discourage wealth addiction.[20]
Much
earlier, Aristotle was aware of this human inability to contain the wealth
drive.
It would appear… that [the
acquisition of] all wealth must have a limit. In actual experience, however, we
see the opposite happening. All who are engaged in the acquisition increase
their fund of currency without any limit or pause…
Aristotle’s
diagnosis is:
The
fundamental cause of this state of mind is concern about living, rather than
about living well.[21]
Mill
also had a diagnosis of this malaise of the human condition:
When
people who are tolerably fortunate in their outward lot do not find in life sufficient
enjoyment to make it valuable to them, the cause generally is, caring for
nobody but themselves… Next to selfishness, the principal cause which makes
life unsatisfactory is want of mental cultivation.” [22]
Traditional
ethico-legal systems were generally quite focused concerned with the problem of
wealth addiction. Firstly, they insisted upon
instilling a belief the temporality of the world and the immortality of
the human soul. Emphasizing the temporality of the world and the immortality of
the soul, goes a long way to change one’s approach to wealth, and contributes
to reducing the tendency that human beings have for wealth addiction. The
Enlightenment, interestingly, adopts an agnostic position on these questions
which are historically the most significant determinant of a person’s approach
to wealth. Secondly, while they acknowledged the right to private property and
free trade, traditional ethico-legal systems banned some of the most
destructive forms of wealth creation - usury, gambling and purely speculative
trading. Finally, they saddled those who are “tolerably fortunate” with
obligations to take care of other besides themselves, if only in some small
measure. These obligations began with what one owed to one’s biological kin and
often went on to whole community through systems of tithes (ushar) and alms (zakat)etc.
Once law
is divorced from ethics, it is no longer possible to foster communities based
on that ethic of of brotherhood which the ethico-legal systems once promoted.
Going beyond the island of self through giving is a courageous and fulfilling
act but also a difficult one. In our best moments, most of us want to do what
is good. But the problem is that without the supporting arm of the law, nudging
us, this does not usually happen; ethics generally fails to make human beings
take the final plunge that is needed to get off wealth addiction. We are
freedom-loving creatures. But sometimes we need some “big brother” to hold our
hands; let’s confess it.
PART III
The Counter-Revolutions of the
Enlightenment
The
Enlightenment project of reconstructing the law on the basis of ethical
philosophy has generated two powerful epistemological counter-revolutions:
scriptural fundamentalism and anti-legal spiritualism. Let me examine these
briefly, before I go on to propose my own alternative.
1.
Scriptural Fundamentalism: The Problem in Doing Law without Justice:
Like
the Enlightenment, scriptural fundamentalism too draws a wedge between law and
ethics instead of viewing the two as deeply inter-related. Both pit law and
ethic against each other; the only difference is that whereas in the
Enlightenment version, ethical philosophy trumps the Law, in scriptural
fundamentalism, the Law trumps ethical philosophy. What neither can imagine is
a relationship where the law feeds off ethical philosophy and ethical
philosophy feeds off the law. Scriptural fundamentalists are willing to allow
no independent normativity to anything other than scripture; neither Reason,
nor Nature, nor Society, nor History are allowed to have any acknowledged role
in developing an understanding of the ethico-legal obligations imposed by God.
Fundamentalism
is not a post-Enlightenment phenomenon. Its seeds have always been there since
the rise of the great scriptures. Part of the ministry of the prophet Jesus, it
may be recalled, was to wrest the Law from those the stranglehold of the narrow
legalists – the Pharisees – who were keeping it from a more wholesome fulfillment.
Jesus says:
Don’t suppose that I came to do
away with the Law and the Prophets. I did not come to do away with them, but to
give them their full meaning. Heaven and earth may disappear. But I promise you
that not even a period or comma will ever disappear from the Law. Everything
written in it must happen. If you reject even the least important command in
the Law and teach others to do the same, you will be the least important person
in the kingdom of heaven. But if you obey and teach others its commands, you
will have an important place in the kingdom. You must obey God’s commands
better than the Pharisees and the teachers of the Law obey them. [23]
The Quran too
sought to shift the focus of attention from the Law to the Spirit. So, in the
most central aspect of the Law, ie. prayer, it emphasizes not its ritual form,
which varies amongst the scriptural communities, but rather its meaning for
individuals and communities:
To every people have We appointed
ways of worship which they observe. Therefore let them not dispute this matter
with thee, but bid them to thy Lord for thou art on the right way: but if they
debate with thee, then say: God best knoweth what you do! He will judge between
you on the Day of Resurrection, as to the matter wherein ye differ. [24]
Amongst those who the Enlightenment has failed most
totally, notably the world’s poorest communities, fundamentalism has
experienced a great resurgence. These fundamentalists explain the defeat of
their scriptural communities at the hands of the Enlightenment-inspired
colonizers, as the result of a deviation from “pure” scriptural law. Scriptural
law, the fundamentalist complain, became contaminated over the course of
history by interpretations which incorporated the ethical reasoning of the
community of believers into the law; they are, in this regard, similar to
Kantians who complain about the contamination of ethical thought by empirical
knowledge. Scriptural fundamentalists seek redemption through revival of “pure”
scriptural Law, just as Kantians seeks redemption through “pure” Ethics.
Fundamentalists also strive to keep the Law pure by preventing the insights
offered by the modern sciences of nature, history and society from percolating into
scriptural interpretation. At the root of fundamentalism lies the idea that
scripture is the soles locus of divine revelation in the world and must
therefore be understood independently of anything else.
The
problem with fundamentalism is that what it seeks in the scriptures, the
scriptures refuse to grant: direct answers to the problems of the day. Scriptural
tradition records the memory of an epoch when God would speak directly to
people and answered their questions; but they also tell us that that era is
gone. In the archetype of scriptural traditions, Judaism, the Prophet Moses is
lovingly remembered as someone who would have spontaneous conversations with
God; but that epoch ends with the revelation of the Ten Commandments, written
on a stone tablet. The scriptures gained significance in the human ethico-legal
quest precisely when it was no longer possible to converse with God directly, ie.
when the world was, in Weber’s words, becoming disenchanted. The scriptures are
texts that can be read; they are not oracles that can be heard. Texts do not
answer our questions back the way oracles did; but texts can be made to answer
our questions through the intermediation of interpretative reasoning. The
exercise of interpretation necessarily involves Reason. And Reason, even when
it is acting upon scripture, is necessarily affected by understanding of
Nature, Society and History. In short, the “pure” Law that fundamentalists seek
from scripture, scripture cannot provide.
That
God chose to reveal himself in texts and in texts which are so evidently prone
to multiple meanings means that it is impossible to retrieve “Law” pure of the
influences of Reason, Nature Society and History. One can pretend to do so, but
it would only be a false pretension. No less than any other set of interpreters
of scripture, fundamentalists too bring to the table their understandings of
Reason, Nature, Society and History into the interpretation of the Law; it is
just they are less conscious of these understandings and thus less careful
about them; often what they infuse into scripture, although unconsciously, are
understanding of Reason, Nature and Society which are simply out-dated.
Not
only is fundamentalism ultimately unsuccessful in achieving what it seeks –
pure Law – it also leads to a terrible waste of human capacity for
self-conscious, careful and disciplined reasoning. Many scholars are of the
view that the reason why, after a certain point in history, God has chosen to
reveal his Law only through scriptures is because He wants human beings to
exert their reason and develop. Reason is a like a muscle; it grows with
exertion. One of the finest examples of the exertions of human Reason known to
the history of civilization is scriptural legal reasoning, as any reader of
classical Islamic, Jewish and Catholic natural law texts would attest. Interpreter
who are engaged in synchronizing their understanding of scriptural Law, Ethical
Reason, Nature, Society and History are often exemplars of the intellectual and
spiritual musicality which the human race is capable of; fundamentalism, on the
other hand, is characterized by the lack of these attractive features.
A
not unexpected result of this undoing of historical evolution is that the
“pure” version of Law which is discovered appears antithetical to the
prevailing ethical rationality; if feels unjust because it is mixing with the
Law notions of justice which no longer uphold. Whatever their claim to “purity”
may be worth, the truth is that instead of striving to make scriptural Law more
accessible in the intellectual idiom of our times, fundamentalists make it seem
more remote and unintelligible. If so few people in the world today can see the
charm of scriptural legal reasoning, a lion’s share of blame goes to the
fundamentalists who have hijacked it, without projecting its true spirit.
2.
Spiritualism: The Problem with Giving Up on the Law
Yet
another way to resolve the tension between law and ethics is Spiritualism.
Spiritualism represents a completion rejection of the possibilities of the Law.
While Enlightenment projects seek to replace the Law with rationalist ethics,
Spiritualism replaces the Law with simple personal intuition, the call of the
heart. From the spiritualist perspective, one is not supposed to follow the Law
but only the spirit behind it. The idea is that since all situations are
particular and different, deriving a solution for them from the scriptures is pointless.
For each ethico-legal question faced by the individual, the right answer to the
can be found only through personal intuition which is conceived of as a form of
divine revelation. The focus of spiritualism is on developing personal
intuition rather than on cultivating a better understanding of reason, nature,
history and society.
While
it is hard to deny the continuing presence of persons who are able to divine
answers to ethico-legal questions through mystical experience, such experience
is by definition incommunicable. As we have noted above, in the era of the
scriptures, the value of such experience has been greatly reduced. The spirit
can no longer claim self-sufficiency from the Law. The pursuit for the spirit
has not to be conducted within the four corners of the law.
Furthermore,
spiritualism threatens to undermine one of the most seminal contributions of
scriptural religion in human history: the universalization of rationality.
Whereas in earlier eras of human history, different castes and tribes looked to
the guidance and intermediation of different gods and oracles, the scriptures
provided all human being with a single source of divine guidance, thus laying
the foundation for universal rationality; and that in turn led to the idea of a
true human equality. The foundations of a truly global human civilization can
be traced back to the Bible and the Quran because these texts popularized the
idea that the truth that is not just true for one people, it is trueor all
people. By denying the primacy of widely
shared scriptures, and by elevating personal experiential insights of
individual, spiritualism roll backs on the universalization brought about by
the scriptures. At worst, it leads to a divided society where every individual
lives in his or her own moral universe; at best, it leads to a society composed
of small, close-knit spiritual cults. What spiritualism has never delivered,
and cannot deliver, is a universal human community with a shared ethico-legal
sense.
PART IV
Scriptural Legal Tradtions and
Prospect of Bridging the Ethico-Legal Divide
The
scriptures of the Abrahamic tradition begin with the assertion that there is
only one God, the God of the Heavens and the Earth, who is Just and all–Knowing.
Because He loves human beings, He has done the thinking for them and formulated
a Law which best serves them in their pursuit of happiness. The theological
arguments for the existence of such a god, or the just or unjust nature of the
Law He has proclaimed are not a matters of present concern to us. What we do contend,
however, is that the surest foundations of ethico-legal communities have been
laid by the scripture which are revealed (or at least claim to be revealed) by
the one God. It is far from a coincidence that what the morally awakened minds
have always sought for on earth and never really found, only the heavens have supplied.
This has something to do with the very structure of human experience-based
reason.
Whenever
the awakened human being looks for ethico-legal truth using experience and ethical
reasoning alone, he soon confronts an inconvenient fact: the ethical
conclusions he arrives at depend upon the presuppositions which he begins from.
This means that if he had used other presuppositions, his conclusions would
have been different. The presupposition in any ethical argument is an ethical
value; and the thing about the ethical values is that there is there is not one
but many of them, and often the values compete with each other. So, for
instance, you can either maximize liberty or equality; arguments which maximize
lead one lead to opposite conclusions; both are perfectly logical, but the end
up leading to an unresolved conflict.
Ethical
reason is necessarily indeterminate because, on its own, it has no way of
reconciling the conflict of values which is so evident in the world.
Max
Weber noted this limitation of purely rational forms of pleading in the realm
of ethics with great clarity in his lecture “Science as a Vocation”. He
observed: “'Scientific'
pleading
is
meaningless
in
principle
because
the
various
value
spheres
of
the
world
stand
in
irreconcilable
conflict
with
each
other…” This seemingly irreconcilable conflict of
values in the modern world has a close parallel in human history: ancient polytheist
cultures. Polytheism is what happens when human being infer the presence of
divinity from what they see around them – a world of many different forces.
Weber quotes the elder Mill who said: “If
one
proceeds
from
pure
experience,
one
arrives
at
polytheism.” Weber also notes another fact which we
know about polytheistic cultures such as the Greeks and the Hindus: they viewed
the world as plagued by gods conflicting with each other, and vying for the
allegiance of human beings. Likewise, today, diverging values compete for our
loyalty. He also notes that over the course of human history, the only force
that has successfully dethroned the warring pantheons of polytheism is genuine “religious
prophecy”. The prophets liberated their people from
the clutches of warring gods, helping them focus on the “one thing that is
needful”. Prophesy alone possesses the ability to instill the “grandiose
rationalism” which is needed to lay the foundation
of “an
ethical
and
methodical
conduct
of
life”. Referring to Christianity’s historical
triumph over paganism, he says “for
a
thousand
years,
our eyes had been blinded
by
the
allegedly
or
presumably
exclusive
orientation
towards
the
grandiose
moral
fervor
of
Christian
ethics.” But, in the wake of the Enlightenment that
exclusive orientation was lost. As a result, the conflict of values is back in
town: “’[m]any
old
gods
ascend
from
their
graves;
they
are
disenchanted
and
hence
take
the
form
of
impersonal
forces.
They
strive
to
gain
power
over
our
lives
and
again
they
resume
their
eternal
struggle
with
one
another….”[25]
For
far too long, scholars in the field of law and ethics have evaded Weber’s grim
but sparklingly lucid diagnosis of the fate of our times. What we see going on amongst
various theorist of justice is precisely a “war of the gods”. Some theorists
favour liberty; others favour equality; and so on. Each has worked out his or
her system down to the finest details. None of the theorists can be shown to be
“wrong”; it is only they are priests of different “gods” or what Weber called
different “value sphere”.
It
seems to me only natural to conclude that the Just Law which we are looking for
can only be found in the scriptures that record revelations from heaven
received by the great prophets. Where we differ interminably based upon a
conflict of ethical values, the scriptures offer to definitively settle the
matter, one way or the other. In that sense, Scriptural law alone offers the
prospect of a law that enjoys a normativity independent of the conflicting ethical
values of its interpreter. In that
sense, scripture provides an ideal ground in which to pursue our search for
Just Law – a law which is capable of having a two-way, reciprocal relationship
with ethical reasoning, rather than getting trumped by it all the time.
But
scriptures, as we have noted above, do not speak us directly; they may record
the speech of God, but that God has, since the era of Moses, ceased to hold
intimate conversations with human beings. Today, we have to resort to far more demanding
methods of discovering exactly what it is that God has decreed. The scriptures
bring us close to Just Law, but they cannot get us all the way. For that we
need a powerful epistemology that unlocks the truths locked up in the texts.
Not
only do the scriptures offer a fertile ground in our search for Just Law, they
are the places where Just Law is most desperately needed. As a result of its
integration with ethics, in scriptural traditions and especially in juridical
religions, the Law comes to play an unusually critical role in the daily life
of believers. Contemporary common law and civil are only codes of law; it is
possible for their subjects to have a completely independent sense of ethics.
But the shariah, the halakha, the
dharma, and even traditional tribal
laws are as much codes of morality as they are codes of law; this is why I have
referred to them as ethico-legal traditions rather than legal stems. In these
traditions, not only does the Law define the rules for adjudication of rights
(such as matters between ruler and the ruled, and contracting parties), it comes
to define the entire meaning of what is “right”. From the time she wakes up on
her bed to the time she goes to sleep and from the moment she gains consciousness
to the moment she dies, every act of the believer is seen to possess a legal
dimension. The thoughtful Muslim, Jew or Brahmanical Hindu, finds herself
living in a far more intensely juridical universe than someone for who law and
ethics are neatly compartmentalised. It is for the believer in these
traditions, more than for anyone else, that a proper epistemology of the Law is
a matter of urgent and practical importance. A corrupted vision of the law is
here doubly destructive: it destroys the pursuit of happiness here on earth and
also dampens prospect of salvation in eternity.
PART V
Just
Law: Theory and Application
1.
A Proposed Epistemology for Discovering Just Law:
Having
presented an extended critique of key Enlightenment projects, and the counter-Enlightenment
projects of fundamentalism and spiritualism, it falls upon the critic to
perform the far more demanding task presenting an alternative approach to the
human ethico-legal quest. As argued in Parts I, I and III, what we need is
neither pure Justice, nor pure Law but Just Law. And as argued in Part IV, the
best starting point in this search are the scriptures which record heavenly
revelations to the prophets about the law of God.
But
the scriptures, as we have noticed above, do not speak to us; they cannot tell
us what is good and just in the same sense that oracles once did. So how is
scriptural law to be understood? What shall the epistemology of a Just Lawyer
be?
A
- Acknowledging the Role of Reason, including Ethical Reason in Law
To
begin with, it must be boldly acknowledged that the source of Just Law is not
Revelation per se; rather, the source
of Just Law is Reason, including ethical reason. For far too long, scriptural
interpretation has been disguised as the product of Revelation alone, and
marketed as a recipe of deliverance from the errors and failings to which Reason
is prone. This view of scriptural interpretation serves the political agenda of
drawing rigid binaries between “Modern Science” and “Traditional Religion”,
providing rallying slogans to bigots on both side of the divide. But it needs
to be discarded because it is inaccurate: as discussed in Section III, all
interpretation is inevitably affected by the reasoning of the interpreter.
Furthermore, underemphasizing the role of Reason may have been helpful in
another age but, in this Age of Reason, it is extremely unhelpful. Finally,
understating the importance of reason in scriptural interpretation runs against
the message of the scriptures themselves because the the scriptures exert upon believers
to exert their reason. The last of the great revealed books, the Quran, is
ahead of all others in this regard. Relying upon the work of Muhammad Iqbal,
the prominent 20th century Islamic philosopher, a contemporary
scholar states:
It
is difficult to find a non-philosophical text in world literature which
discusses the topic of reason as often and in as much depth as the Qur’an. The
complementary relationship between wahy [Revelation] and ‘aql [Reason] is
illustrated by the way that the Qur’an continually exhorts human beings to use
their ‘aql properly. On nearly 24 occasions the Qur’an condemns those who
deprive themselves of the light and guidance contained in wahy because they
misuse their ‘aql. While it never explicitly says that human reason is “light”
or “guidance,” on nearly 60 different occasions the Qur’an does say that that
“light” and “guidance” (i.e. revelation) cannot be properly understood without
the aid of reason.[26]
The Islamic tradition is characterized by two complementary
claims: firstly, the reality of prophesy is affirmed and the origins of the law
are traced back to prophesy; but, secondly, it is also affirmed that the
Prophet of Islam is the last of the prophet and the doors of prophesy are with
him now closed forever. This closing of the doors of prophesy is what elevates
Reason to its present position as the foremost (though not exclusive) aid in
our ethico-legal enquiries. Iqbal states:
The Prophet of Islam seems to stand
between the ancient and the modern world. In so far as the source of his
revelation is concerned, he belongs to the ancient word [the world of
prophesy]; in so far as the spirit of his revelation is concerned he belongs to
the modern world. In him life discovers … sources of knowledge [other than
revelation]….” [27]
So
what are these other sources of knowledge without which it is no longer
possible to properly under the ethico-legal message of the scriptures. Iqbal
identifies at least two:
According to the Qur’an, there are
two other sources of knowledge – Nature and History; it is in tapping these
sources of knowledge the spirit of Islam is seen at its best…[T]he constant
appeal to reason and experience in the Qur’an, and the emphasis it lays on
Nature and History as sources of human knowledge……
B
– Absorbing the Insights of Nature and History into the Law
Let us first
consider the role of Nature in our ethico-legal enquiries. The truth is that
for most of the history of the Western philosophical tradition, Nature has
remained a point of reference in answering the ethico-legal question. The
questions of “what is good?” and “what is natural?” have been viewed as deeply
related questions. The cues of nature –
studied by scientists – were used in the determination of morality and law, by
jurists and philosophers alike. Aristotle’s works represent the most ardent
such attempt, his repeated refrain being: “nature makes nothing purposeless or
in vain…” Aristotle tries to work out the just solution in four fundamental
human relationships which he encountered in Hellenic society: master-slave,
man-woman, ruler-ruled and teacher-pupil based upon his understanding of
nature. But it was not just philosophers who took cognizance of the insights
offered by nature; jurists also took stock of these insights. See, for
instance, this marvelous passage from the first book of the Institutes of
Justinian:
The law of nature is that law which
nature teaches to all animals. For this law does not belong exclusively to the
human race, but belongs to all animals, whether of the earth, the air, or the
water. Hence comes the union of the male and female, which we term matrimony;
hence the procreation and bringing up of children. We see, indeed, that all the
other animals besides men are considered as having knowledge of this law.[28]
The absolute divorce of ethical philosophy from natural
science is one of the great tragedies of our time. As an exemplar of this
approach, consider Kant. Kant finds “essays on morality written in [a]
fashionable style” bewildering because in these essays, “we run into a
marvelous medley – now the talk is of the particular vocation of human nature
(but along with this also the Idea of a rational nature as such), now they talk
of perfection, now of happiness, here moral feeling and there the fear of God;
a little of this and a little of that. But it never occurs to anyone to ask whether the principles of morality are to be
sought at all in our knowledge of human nature (which we can get only from
experience).”[29]
The last line is obviously rhetorical. For Kant, principles of morality are
not be sought in our knowledge of human nature, at all. For Just Lawyers, that
is not an option because our scriptures refer to human nature as one of the
repositories of ethical truth.
Iqbal also identifies History as a point of
reference in our understanding of scriptural Law. He says:
History or, in the language of the
Qru’an, ‘the days of God’, is the third source of human knowledge, according to
the Qur’an. It is one of the most essential teachings of the Quran that nations
are collectively judged, and suffer for their misdeeds here and now. In order
to establish this proposition, the Quran constantly cites historical instances,
and urges upon the reader to reflect on the past and present experience of
mankind.
One of the ways of determining which of two ethico-legal
concepts are close to truth is to look at their historical career. A close
study of history reveals that certain ethico-legal concepts have contributed to
the destruction of their bearers, either at the hands of nature, or at the
hands of other human beings. In other
word, the truth triumphs in the battlefield of history. Clearly, we cannot
ignore historically triumphant ethico-legal ideas when the try to read our
scriptures.
C
– Absorbing the Insights of Society into the Law: The role of ethico-legal anthropology and the
search for human universals
Finally, in looking for Just Law, we need to take
cognizance of the various commonalities that can be observed amongst societies
widely distributed across time and space. If there is something all or most of
them have agreed upon, it is clearly a cue that cannot be ignored. A popular author
rooted in the Christian traditions observes:
I know some people say the idea of
a Law of Nature or decent behavior known to all men is unsound, because
different civilizations and different ages had quite different moralities. But
this is not true. There have been differences between moralities, but these
have never amounted to anything like a total difference. If anyone will take
the trouble to compare the moral teaching of, say, the ancient Egyptians,
Babylonians, Hindus, Chinese, Greeks and Romans, what will really strike him
will be how very like they are to each
other and to our own. [30]
In this regards, Just Lawyers need to take stock of
the work of ethico-legal anthropologists who have gone a long way to further
our understanding of human universals. For instance, Donald Brown, a famous
anthropologist, identifies around four hundreds human universals which he
claims can be found amongst all the societies that anthropologists have studied
in the last century.[31] Ultimately,
the question of universals is a
definitional one; and the answers to such questions can never be agreed upon.
Yet, a Just Lawyer interpreting the scriptures can gainfully be informed about
what it is the societies across the span of time and space seem to be agreeing
upon. Surely, there has to be some truth to it.
3.
Two Approaches to Just Law: An Example
from the annals Islamic Jurisprudence
Let
me contrast two approaches to ethico-legal epistemology from within the
glorious tradition of Islamic tradtion. Firstly, consider this approach which
draws a simplistic rigid binary between Law (based on revelation) and Ethics
(based on reason); once the binary is drawn, the former is made to trump the
latter:
The question arises, ‘Is it
possible for the mind alone, unaided by God’s messengers and revealed
scriptures, to know God’s rulings …? Or is this impossible?’
The position of the Ash’aris is that the mind
is unable to know the rule of Allah about the acts of those morally responsible
except by means of His messengers and scriptures…[T]he good of the acts of
those morally responsible is what the [Divine] Lawgiver has indicated is good
by permitting it or asking it to be done. And the bad is what the Lawgiver has
indicted is bad by asking it not be done. The good is not what reason considers
good, nor the bad what reason considers bad. The measure of good and bad… is the Sacred Law, not reason. [32]
This last sentence categorically invokes a binary
understand of Sacred Law and ethical reason. It is assumed that the answer to
the human ethico-legal question can be found in either of the two; what has not been considered is the
possibility that the answer could be discovered by both, each acting in tandem
with the other, behaving in a relational and non-antagonistic manner. This
possibility might have eluded the author because of an ill-assessment of the
powers of ethical reason. He writes:
[T]he mind is unable to know the
rule of Allah… [f]or minds are in obvious disagreement about acts. Some minds
find certain acts good, others find them bad. Moreover, one person can be of
two minds about one and the same action. Caprice often wins over the intellect,
and considering something good or bad comes to be based on mere whim…[33]
More
careful readers the signs of God (ayaat) manifesting in the His Books
(scriptures) and the signs (ayaat) manifesting in the His Work (nature,
society, history) know that things are not that simple. Ibn Aqil (d. ~ 1119), the
eminent eleventh century jurist from the Hambali school of Islamic
jurisprudence, explains this philosophical point beautifully:
God has endowed [his
creatures], for their own welfare, with boundless Reason and with powerful
Instincts impelling them to do what is right and to refrain from evil and
corruption. Consider, for instance, how God has gifted us with a carnal
appetite and an instinctive desire for seeking sexual intercourse. This
instinct is what, indeed, guides us toward the path we necessarily need to
tread for the progress and preservation of our species. Or consider, the
instinctive compassion we feel towards animals, and the revulsion we feel
towards seeing them suffer; this instinct is what makes us refrain from causing
pain to others and what makes us curtail an assailant who does venture to hurt
others. Or consider how it is in our nature to experience joy when Society
lavishes praises upon us for our deeds. Society generally praises only those
deeds that are good and therefore our instinct for praise-seeking acts as
powerful incentive for the performance of good deeds. This in fact is what
drives much of the works that increase utility and ward off pain. God does not
leave good deeds to go without praise from society, thus incentivizing them;
and God does not let evil deeds go without taunts from society, thus
disincentivizing them. Glory be to God… who turns His creatures away from the
course of evil, by various means here on earth, as well as with His menaces of
punishment in the Hereafter.[34]
Here, then, we have an example from within the
Islamic tradition of a jurist whose does not draw rigid binaries between the
urgins of scripture, nature and society; for him, all three are deeply
inter-related and largely reinforcing, each helping us understand the path to
ethico-legal. It is this approach to scripture which offers the best resource
for discovering Just Law, a law that derives strength from nature, society and
history rather than waging a futile war against them.
3.
Applying the Theory of Just Law to Actual Ethico-Legal Issues: A Few
Illustrations
When we incorporate the
insights revealed by Nature, History and Society into our reading of scriptural
legal texts, our appreciation for ethico-legal obligations is considerable
improved; at any rate, our appreciation for these obligations is far better than
it would be if we relied upon either pure ethical reason or scriptural
fundamentalism. In this section, I try and present a few examples to this
effect.
1.
Private Property: Its Existence and Limits
Let
us begin with the obligation to respect private property. While the consensus
in most historically accumulated ethico-legal systems is in its favour, our
scriptures are often not conclusive on the point. They remain open to multiple
interpretations on this point and the debate has never been conclusive. John
Locke, for instance, found himself confronted with a communitarian interpretation
of the Biblical verse which indicates that God “has given the earth to the
children of men”[35]
And in the twentieth century, Quranic verses have also received interpretation
at the hands of Islamic socialists which challenge the consensus position on
private property. Yet, when we move beyond formalist textualism and bring in
the fruits of a careful study of Nature, History and Society, things become
clear. Aided by the work of natural scientists, historians and anthropologist,
the just lawyers can powerful respond the challenges posed by ethical
philosophers.
So
in our present problem, let us consider the insights offered by evolutionary
biology. Evolutionary biologists have documented in great detail the
territorial nature of primates, particularly male primates. Everywhere the primate, especially the male
primate, seeks to mark his territory out from that of others; and in doing this
seemingly selfish act, he contributes positively to the survival of the
species. Just lawyers cannot afford to remains blind to this cue about the
desirability of private property which nature so abundantly furnishes.
Similarly, the performance of the concept of private property in battlefield of
history cannot be ignored. Historians link the fate of Communism with its
approach to private property. Lawyers must take stock of this reality. Finally,
lawyers must also read the account given by anthropologists of societies and
tribes which had more communalistic regimes of property, and the gradual eclipse
of that form of life.
While
our methodology of legal reasoning strengthens the argument in favour of the
existence of private property and market-based exchange, the same methodology alos
strengthens the case for putting limits on the operation of these institutions.
After
concluding that “[m]ost things are the property of individuals who acquire them
in different ways,” the authors of the Institutes of Justinian go on to add
significant exceptions to private property:
[S]ome things by the law of nature are common to
all; some are public; some belong to corporate bodies, and some belong to no
one… By the law of nature these things are common
to mankind---the air, running water, the sea, and consequently the shores
of the sea… Among
things belonging to a corporate body,
not to individuals, are, for instance, buildings in cities, theaters,
race-courses, and other similar places belonging in common to a whole city…
Things sacred, religious, and holy belong
to no one; for that which is subject to divine law is not the property of
any one.[36]
To sum, Just Law’s nuanced epistemology allows us to
both affirm the existence of the institution of private property, while placing
certain limits on its operation. Both concepts rest upon our interpretation of
the texts that have a scriptural position in our traditions, coupled with
insights offered by Nature, History and Society.
2.
Ethics of the Market: Trade, not Usury and Gambling; labour, not slavery
“They
ask you about wine and gambling. Say:
‘There is great sin in them, and also
advantages for people; but their sin is greater than their advantage.’” Qur’an
2:219
…They
say: "Trade is like usury," but Allah hath permitted trade and
forbidden usury… (Qur’an 2:275)
“Love
Thy Neighbor”
[TO BE
COMPLETED]
3.
Gender: Between Equality and Inequality
On the face of it, the human
world today is more divided than ever before along lines of political and
economic power: there are 85 people who own more wealth than half of the
members of our species. This is certainly a far more unequal distribution of
things than the age of Brahmanical rule. But the difference today is in the
realm of ideas: no one today really can really believe that tho 85 persons are
more “human” than the rest of us. One of the great historical currents of our
history the last two to three thousand years has been the re-unification of
tribal and ethnic groups. For the first time in our history since the
scattering of the descendants of Adam and Eve into hundreds of different races
and tribes into one-world, the Roman Empire, the Holy Roman Empire and even
more so the various empires of the Muslim world made the world one. And recently, the forces of modernity which
arose from the cradle of post-Christian Enlightenment Europe are doing away
with what were once deemed indomitable differentiations amongst the human
species, in even more profound ways. Every human being today is one telephone
call away; that sort of a global neighborhood, we have never before had, since
we left the garden of Eden.
Insofar as “races” and “nations”
go, the idea of Equality is a truth revealed by the scriptures as well as History.
The Judeo-Christian and Islamic narratives about the origins of the human
beings records that Adam and Eve were created from a single soul and their
various descendants eventually become not one but many nations. And, not too
long ago, the results of the bloodiest war in human history also stand witness
to this. Those of us who could not fit this truth into our juridical
imagination, and insisted upon Aryan supremacy, are no longer around to tell
their story. The world is unified by the concept that we are all one species
and that all differentiations between us are purely matter of social and
historical coincidence. The ethico-legal significance of this concept is taking
its time sinking in. But at the theoretical level, the idea of Equality has certainly
made our task much simpler.
However, the one cleavage amongst
human beings that is not going away is the one which has its roots in nature
rather than social construction: gender. Both the natural sciences which study
human nature, especially evolutionary psychology and the sciences which study
societies across the breadth of time and space, especially anthropology, are leading
us to this conclusion. Gender may have been understood differently in different
places; but it has always been there. Since the simple formula of equality is
the least help in this area, Just Law will have to work out in great detail how
ethico-legal obligations differ between genders. The declarations of the rights
that came out of Enlightenment ethical reason working in tandem with the
natural law tradition at turn of eighteenth century have stood the test to time,
insofar as their original concerns goes – the state-citizen relation. History
has vindicated their truth. But when the same mind-set was turned towards
understanding problems of a vastly different provenance – especially gender
relationship – the solution has proven extremely naïve. The thought gender too
would become history. But of course it didn’t and is wont.
This does not mean that we can
blithely return to the inherited rules of our scriptural tradition either.
Insofar as those rules are concerned, feminists have a point. The influence of
patriarchal society in their formulation is undeniable. The different task
awaiting Just Lawyers in this century, therefore, is to extricate the corpus of
scriptural law from the effects of patriarchal mindset and stripping it down to
the level which is warranted by the lessons of Reason, History and Society.
This would require from Just Lawyers not only a re-examination of scriptural
texts but also a thorough immersion in the natural and historical sciences
which deal with gender. When we are done with it, the core of ethico-legal
rules about gender will certainly not be equality, but it will be much close to
equality than earlier centuries had thought.
4.
The Meaning of the Obligation to Pray:
Other than faith in the unity of the Divine being,
there is nothing that the ethico-legal tradition of Islam emphasizes more than
the performance of prayer (salat), individual as well as congregation. The
Prophet Muhammad is reported to have said: Prayer is the foundation of
religion. So the way any particular school of thought approaches the concept of
prayer is greatly indicative of its entire approach to the ethico-legal
tradition.
The
human instinct for worship is one of those instincts which Enlightenment law
has consistently refused to acknowledge. Human beings do not just love liberty,
fraternity and equality; most of them also love worshiping someone higher than
themselves. Prayer is an ethico-legal imperative that human beings have
acknowledged for much of their history. Any system of Just Law cannot be
founded by shutting our eyes to this ethico-legal reality. The result of the
Enlightenment’s refusal to deal with the instinct for worship is that prayer
has been relegated to the level of individual action; in that sense, the
Enlightenment has helped further the growth of spiritualism, with all its
dilemmas mentioned above.
Fundamentalists
too have failed to provide a compelling way to deal with the human instinct for
worship. They view prayer in purely legal terms. From their perspective, the
obligation to pray exists only because the law commands so and for no other
reason. It is akin to a contractual obligation between man and God: man prays
in a certain prescribed manner, and God rewards man in return. It follows from
this that the focus of man in the performance of prayer needs to be on the
ritual formalities which ensure that his liability to God is fully discharge;
and so that if his performance is only partial,
constituting part performance, he may be able to do what it takes to
make it whole. This purely legal approach. runs quite contrary to our
scriptural texts. Prophet Muhammad described prayer not as a ritual but as “the
coolness of his eyes”. The Quran refers to the prayer as a balm for the hearts.
It says: Indeed it is in the remembrance of God that the hearts find tranquility.
But
those scriptural legal interpreters who are open to incorporating the insights
of Nature, Society and History are able to present a far more compelling view
of prayer as an essential part of a fulfilling human life. The great Indian
theologian Muhammad Iqbal presents one such perspective in his essay of The
Meaning of Prayer.
Firstly,
alluding to the insights into human nature offered by modern psychologists such
as William James, he concludes: “[P]sychologically speaking, prayer is
instinctive in its origin… Prayer as a means of spiritual illumination is a
normal vital act by which the little island of our personality suddenly
discovers its situation in a larger whole of life…[W]hether individual or
associative, [it] is an expression of man's inner yearning for a response in
the awful silence of the universe...".
Secondly,
he alludes to lessons from the history of human spirituality across various
societies: “[T]he modern mind… demands a concrete living experience of God. And
the history of the race shows that the attitude of the mind embodied in the act
of worship is a condition for such an experience.”
Finally,
he draws a connection between prayer and the proper growth of the human
intellectual faculties: “In fact, prayer must be regarded as a necessary
complement to the intellectual activity of the observer of Nature. The
scientific observation of Nature keeps us in close contact with the behavior of
Reality, and thus sharpens our inner perception for a deeper vision of it… The
truth is that all search for knowledge is essentially a form of prayer.” [37]
When
these multi-faceted insights are brought to bear upon the scriptural texts
about the obligation to pray, they give a new life to it. And it also becomes much
easier to tell apart the spiritual essence of the obligation imposed from its
ritual expterior. So, based upon the foregoing, Iqbal is able to claim in a
later part of the same essay: "The form of prayer ought not to become a
matter of dispute. Which side you turn your face is certainly not essential to
the spirit of prayer. The Quran is perfectly clear on this point..."[38] A
Just Law epistemology makes it easier to understand why it is that the great
books of our ethico-legal tradition devote such a major part to the rituals of
prayers – because the law of prayer helps us deal with our ‘worship instinct’
in a fulfilling way, just as the law of contracts and torts helps us deal with
our economic instincts or the law of marriage helps us deal with our sexual
instincts.
PART VI
What Just Law Promises to Just
Lawyers
1.
Giving a new meaning to the legal profession and legal education.
Today,
a concern about “justice” might seem the primary or even exclusive concern of
philosophers and politicians, not lawyers but it is important to recall that
this has not always been the case. For most of our history, lawyers as well as
lay people held a far more lofty conception of the legal calling. It is my
contention that lawyers’ fall from grace has much to do with the
Enlightenment’s divorce between law and ethics; conversely, one of the promises
of the Just Law approach I have proposed is that it offers to give their
calling a new meaning.
Historically,
it was the juridical religions – Judaism, Islam and, to a certain extent,
Brahmanical Hinduism – which offered the loftiest conception of legal calling.
The juridical religions are ethico-legal traditions, where the universal
questions about justice and goodness are answered, mostly though not
exclusively, through some notion of the “Law”. The Law itself is viewed as
nothing less than a manifestation of divine wisdom, an articulation in humanly
intelligible ways of the inner order of the cosmos. The shariah, the halakha, the
dharma, and even traditional tribal
laws are as much codes of morality as they are codes of law. In often
short-lived era of the prophets, it was the prophets who spoke to their
communities who spoke about the meaning of law and justice. But in the much
longer inter-prophetic eras, and post-prophetic era, the job of discovering what is good and just
has usually been assigned to jurists. It is understand therefore, the fuqaha, the Rabbis and the shastris were
view no mere white-collar technicians; being expositors of the true meaning of
justice and goodness in the universe, they were viewed as no less than the inheritors of the charisma of the
prophet. And it is for similar reasons that traditional education for Muslims,
Jews and Brahmanical Hindus, was first and foremost, a legal education: fiqh, Talmud and shastars.
While
this conception was most obvious in the juridical religions, it was not unique
to them. Take, for instance, this statement about the relationship between law
and justice with which begins Justinian’s Digest or the Pandects, the most
important text that influenced the training of most young lawyers in the
Western world (outside England) for more than a millennium:
A
law student at the outset of his studies ought first to know the derivation of
the word jus (law). Its derivation is from the justitia (justice). For, in terms of Celsius’ elegant definition, the law is the art of goodness and fairness.
Of that art we [jurists] are deservedly called the priests.[39]
Clearly
Roman jurists held a far more lofty conception of their calling than what we
now have. The authors of the Digest make a comment which reveals this lofty
self-perception:
…We
[jurists] cultivate the virtue of justice and claim awareness of what is good
and fair, discriminating between fair and unfair, distinguishing lawful from
unlawful, aiming to make men good not only through fear of penalties but also
indeed under allurement of rewards, and affecting
a philosophy which, if I am not deceived, is genuine, not sham.[40]
These excerpts from the Pandects should be
sufficient to illustrate that far more than philosophers and theologians, it
was our predecessors in the legal profession who shouldered the burden of
telling society about what is “good” and what is “bad” and of teaching that
genuine “philosophy” which underlies the whole edifice of the law and without
which no legal tradition can go to thrive for long.
Why
is it that lawyers today cannot have a similarly conception of their calling?
Clearly, this has much to do with the Enlightenment’s divorce between law and
ethics. The lawyers who wrote and taught the Pandects believed in the ethical
philosophy underlying their law; this is why they thought of their calling as
expounding “the art of goodness and
fairness.” In the post-Enlgithenment, however, very few of us sincerely
believe that about our calling. It is true that our historically accrued bodies
of law - English common law, the Roman civil law and the legal heritages of
juridical religions – continue to exist. But, since we are failing in our duty
as lawyers to expound the ethical philosophy which underlies these laws, But
they have lost the ethical hold which they once exerted upon the hearts of men.
And increasingly, historically evolved jurists’ law, is being altered, if not
altogether replaced, by statutory codes, drafted and promulgated by
politicians. Instead, even with the
legal community, as soon as the accrued body of legal rulings in our traditions
falls out of tune with the tests set by Kant and Bentham, they lose all
respect. When the law is no longer views as the source of ethical values, and
when lawyers willingly surrender the ethical component of our ethico-legal
traditions, then it only natural that our job will be confined to the dull
business of determining the outcomes of cases on the basis of what law the
state puts in front of us, or, worst still, as the legal realists prescribe,
simply predicting the behavior officials. The public too returns the favour.
Once lawyers concede the possibility that justice can be determined without
reference to the law, they become dispensible. They can be more fruitfully
replaced by philosophers hoping to advance certain values or politicians hoping
to further certain interest. Indeed, in most countries of the world, the
replacement of judge-made law by legislative codes has considerably diminished
the social and political prestige of lawyers. Even in the few jurisdictions of
the world where the legal class continues to enjoy some prestige, their
prestige depend more on their role as advocates of specific political and
economic causes, i.e. as cause lawyers, than it does on their claim to offering
insights on the meaning of law and justice. Modern day American may have a
million strong army of lawyers, and produces 40,000 new lawyers every passing
year. But not one of them enjoys the intellectual or social prestige that Sir
Edward Coke or William Blackstone once enjoyed and which exerted so profound an
influence upon the political vision of America’s founding fathers.
One
of the greatest promises of Just Law is that promises to restore a greater
sense of meaning to the legal calling. If Just Lawyers play their role in
reviving their respective ethico-legal traditions which spring from the scriptures,
they will not only contribute to a better appreciation of law and justice in
their societies; they will also expand the scope of the legal profession. Just
Lawyers will no longer be mere handmaidens of politicians and philosophers,
interpreting and enforcing what law the latter throw at them. Just Lawyers will
therefore earn for their profession a better place in the world. And professors
of Just Law will be able to restore to legal education that centrality it once
enjoyed amongst the human and social sciences.
PART
VII: A Note on Philosophical Methodology
Let
me conclude this essay with a note on my philosophical methodology. While the
question that I have tried to to address is a matter of universal significance,
in proposing this theory for the discovery of “just-law”, the resources
I have used are admittedly from a particular tradition – the ethico-lega
tradition of juridical religions, especially Islam. Jurists in the
(pre-fudamentalist) Islamic tradition, as in the Jewish and Hindu traditions,
have generally considered the legal and moral status of human acts as deeply
and somewhat mysteriously inter-related. In their weltanschauung, a legal ruling that is immoral cannot be possibly
be a correct legal ruling, while a moral principle which fails to square major
legal ruling is in itself morally suspect; it is this ethos which I have tried
to utilize in formulating this theory of “just law”. I have deliberately tried
to avoid falling for the simple and rigid binaries of law/morality and reason/revelation
which characterize so much contemporary discourse on law and justice and which
have led to discursive impasses that hurt the highest aspirations of good
people on both sides of the binary. My theory aims to be reparative rather
than deconstructive: its primary focus is vindicate and reaffirm and not
demolish the insights about law and justice which jurists, especially in my own
tradition, have generally held. Yet, such is the nature of reasoning that even
so a modest and deferential a study cannot remain entirely uncritical; my
theory of just law does end up as providing an independent standpoint from
which to critique existing views of our jurists about law and justice, for
whatever that is worth.
THE
END
[1]
Aristotle, Politics, Book I, Chapter
2
[2]
The Holy Bilble, 2 Corinthians, 3:6
[3]
Queen v. Dudley, quoted in Justice: A
Reader, p. 6
[4]
Jeremy Bentham, Principles of Morals and
Legislation, quoted in Justice: A Reader, p. 11)
[5]
Innameul Kant, Groundwork for the
Metaphysics of Morals, quoted in Justice: A Reader, p. 159)
[6]
John Stuart Mill Utilitarianism,
quoted in Justice: A Reader, p. 15
[7] John Stuart, Mill, Utilitarianism, quoted in Justice, p. 17
[8]
Kant, Groundwork, quoted in Justice
[9]
Aristotle, Politics, quoted in Justice
p. 287
[10]
(Aristotle’s Politics, quoted in Justice p. 289
[11]
Hayek, quoted in Justice, p. 80 – 81
[12]
John Finnis, Law Morality and “Sexual
Orientation”
[13]
Germain Grisez,(1993) The Way of the Lord
Jesus, Living a Christian Life
[14] Kant, What Is Enlightenment?
(1784)
[15] John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (1859)
[16]
William Blackstone, Institutes of the Law of England, Of Husband and
Wife(1765-1769)
[17]
Scalia, J, Barnes v. Glen Theatre, Inc.
501 U.S. 560 (1991)
[18]
Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003)
[19]
(http://www.oxfam.org/sites/www.oxfam.org/files/bp-working-for-few-political-capture-economic-inequality-200114-summ-en.pdf)
[20]
SAM POLKJAN, For the Love of Money, New York Times, 2014) http://www.nytimes.com/2014/01/19/opinion/sunday/for-the-love-of-money.html?_r=1
[21]
Aristotle, Politics, p. 27- 28
[22] John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism,
Justice: A Reader, p. 21
[23]
Holy Bible, Matthew, 5: 17 - 18
[24] Quran, 22: 67-69, translated by
Muhammad Iqbal
[25] Max Weber, Science as a Vocation
[26] Basit Bilal Koshul (2013), Muhammad Iqbal, Charles Peirce and
Reclaiming the “Middle Way”, Cambridge Muslim College, Working Paper
[27] Muhammad Iqbal (1933),
Reconstruction of Religious Thought in Islam
[28]
Natural, Common, and Civil Law, Of Things, Institutes
of Justinian, Book I, Chapter II
[29]
Kant, Groundwork
[30] C.S. Lewis, Mere Christianity
[31]
. ( Brown, D.E. 1991. Human universals. New York: McGraw-Hill)
[32] Ahmad Ibn Naqib al-Misri (d.
1368), ‘Umdatul Salik (Reliance of the Traveller), translated by Nuh Ha Mim
Keller (1991) p. a.1.0, a.2.0
[33] Ahmad Ibn Naqib al-Misri (d.
1368), Reliance of the Traveller, translated by Nuh Ha Mim Keller (1991), p.
a.1.0
[34] Ibn Aqil quoted in Khaled Abul
Fadl’s Conference of the Books, which
in turn quotes George Makdisi’s Ibn
‘Aqil; Note: The translation has been significantly to serve the occasion,
although it retains fidelity to the original.
[35]
Holy Bible, Psalms CXV
[36]
Divisions of Things, Of Things, Institutes of Justinian Book II, Chapter I
[37]
Muhammad Iqbal, The Meaning of Prayer, from 'Reconstruction of Religious Thought
in Islam' (Lahore: 1933)
[38]
Muhammad Iqbal, The Meaning of Prayer, from 'Reconstruction of Religious
Thought in Islam' (Lahore: 1933)
[39]
Justinian’s, Book One, Justice and Law, p. 1